I do not, usually, post comments
on books until I have finished them. However, I also believe that rules are
there for the breaking if you have a sufficient cause, so I am going to pass
comment on something I have recently read, but not yet finished.
The book in question is Nigel
Biggar’s ‘In Defence of War’ (Oxford: OUP, 2013). This is a book which is aimed
at all those pacifists out there who think that there can be no justification
for using what is euphemistically called ‘violent coercion’ to achieve their
ends. In an early part of the book Biggar gives some examples of the terrible
things that happen in war – civilians being machine gunned in the Falaise Gap,
for instance, or a description of a casualty from the US Marines who is still
alive, despite having, apparently, only half a body. These, however, are
balanced by some accounts of what happens when war is eschewed, such as
Srebrenica and the massacre of Muslim men.
War, then, according to Biggar,
is nasty and deeply unpleasant, but, as a committed realist, he has to defend
the idea that sometimes it can be justified. In fact, as a Christian ethicist,
he has to go further and argue that war is not only, on occasion, justified,
but actually just, in terms of the just war theory developed by St Augustine
and, in various forms, still with us today. Along the way Biggar has to deal
with assorted pacifist positions, including those of John Howard Yoder and
Stanley Hauerwas, as well as non-religious pacifists, and, so far as I can tell
he is doing so with some style, although in my view he has missed the key
modern nonviolence oriented theologian in Walter Wink.
But I am digressing, somewhat.
One of the most interesting bits of the book so far are when Biggar shows real
engagement with military history, something quite rare among moral philosophers
in my experience. He has, for example, and extensive discussion of who was to
blame for starting the First World War (Germany, in his view) and, in pursuit
of discussion the proportionality clause in the jus in bello part of the just
war theory, he has some interesting comments on generalship.
Biggar includes in this section a
discussion of the planning for El Alamein. In this, the corps commander
describes the duties during the battle of an armoured brigade. They are to
break through the German lines and hold the gap, while the next armoured
brigade rolls through to exploit it. The brigade commander comments ‘that could
cost fifty per cent casualties’. The corps commander responds: ‘The general is
prepared to accept one hundred per cent.’
Biggar notes that the general in
question was Montgomery, who, despite any flaws which we might need to argue
about (alongside whether he was actually any good) was immensely popular with
his men. Part of this popularity was because the men believed that he would not
waste their lives unnecessarily. Indeed, while not being a World War Two aficionado,
when he came to command in Normandy, I believe that he could not be wasteful
with lives as the British were pretty well at the end of their manpower
reserves. Major losses could not be replaced at that point, and he had to
substitute boots for guns.
How, then, do we deal with this
apparent contradiction? It is not, incidentally, just Montgomery who behaved in
this way. Douglas Haig is widely slated as disregarding the lives and welfare
of his men. And yet Haig is documented as having visited units before the start
of the Somme and having been prevented by his staff from visiting hospitals and
aid stations after the start of the battle because the sights of his first
visit practically incapacitated him.
So there appears to be a
contradiction between the battle planning of the generals and their
compassionate response to their men.
It seems to me that this might
shed some light on why people respond somewhat negatively to wargaming as a
hobby. Generals, it is widely believed in modern culture, are callous. They are
ready and willing to put the lives of their men on the line without a care for
their wellbeing, just to achieve something like an abstract breakthrough, or to
gain a few yards of Flanders mud. It is not often mentioned that generals are often
deeply concerned about their troops, and this not just because well fed and
rested soldiers are better fighters.
In wargaming terms, of course, we
can simply act as entirely callous generals. We can accept, for no particularly
good reason, horrendous casualties among our troops because they are the
perfect stoic warriors, with no dependents, and infinitely replaceable. While
real world generals can be concerned about their men, at least before and after
planning for the battle, wargamers do not have to do this.
Is there a sense here, then, that
we are actually callous towards the real world battles (or, indeed, fictional
ones) and the suffering that they inflict upon the participants? Our little
lead troops are magnificently unswayed by either victory or defeat, in a way
that real soldiers are not. As wargamers, when we concede defeat we can simply
pack the little men away until next time, while a losing general has to deal
with the shreds of his army, try to pull himself and them together, mount a rear
guard action and so on. He also has to explain why he lost to political masters
and, possibly, be vilified in the press and sacked.
I suspect that I have mentioned
before that the context for these post battle activities is a campaign game,
and I do wonder sometimes whether wargamers shy away from campaigns because it
would engage them in these wider, and more ethical, considerations. On the
other hand I confess that most of my campaign games handle these matters at an
abstract level, and so I would be as guilty of ignoring them as the next
wargamer.
But it is an interesting book.