In the philosophy of science,
there is a concept of having two blades to attack any given problem with. The
first blade, normally considered to be the lower one, is empirical data. By
this we mean the stuff experimenters generate. The upper blade is theory, the
results of what Galileo described as the ‘mathematization of nature’ (I am sure
it is more elegant in Latin).
So, for example, the concept of
the Higgs boson was from the upper blade, that is, it was a theoretical
construct, derived from a mathematical model of the universe, or some small (or
very small, in this case) part of it. The lower blade required the construction
of an extremely large, expensive and complex experiment at CERN, the efforts of
hundreds of scientists and engineers and a good deal of media coverage.
Fortunately for all involved, the
two blades met and a bit of the model of the universe was verified, to cheers
and mutual backslapping all around and the dishing out of Nobel prizes to
everyone.
Science, however, is a bit more
complex than that. For example, the derivation of the theoretical model of the
Higgs boson was based on the standard model of sub-atomic particles, which had
been experimentally verified, in smaller but still hugely complex experiments, which
were based on theories which in turn were based on experiments. And so on, back
to Aristotle dropping stones and noting that they all fell downwards.
Of course, there are oddities and
unexplained phenomena abounding in science. The fact is that these anomalies
tend to be parked on a shelf until there is the interest and resource available
to investigate them. I am, in fact, the proud possessor of such an anomaly,
although I do not expect that anyone is going to be interested enough to try to
resolve it in the next century or so. However, it is still there, in the
literature, should anyone be interested enough to give it a go.
History, too, could be suggested
to have this twin blade effect. We do have historical data, in the forms of
documents and artefacts from past times. For example, we have Herodotus’
account of the Battle of Marathon. We also have some archaeology from the site
of the battle, we have some bits of accounts of the paintings in Athens of the
battle, possible a few Persian like objects from Delphi, and so on. Data is in
existence, it just is not very complete.
We also have a set of
expectations about humanity in general. We know, for example, that soldiers
need to eat, and so some provision needs to be made for this. We also know that
horses need feeding as well, and are rather less good at not eating for a cause
than humans are. Thus, theoretically, we have our upper blade. The Persian army
at Marathon needed feeding, as did the cavalry which was present. This leads to
constraints on the numbers of horses that could be present, and also on where
the cavalry camp was positioned in order to provide grazing. Furthermore, of
course, humans can carry their own water; it is better if horses are led to it.
Thus, the two blades of history
start to close a bit. The data gives us, working upwards, as set of
possibilities for what happened. How we interpret this data is constrained by
how reliable we think the writer is, how close to the action, how likely to be
misinformed, and so on. Similarly, artefacts, while useful, can be misleading.
However, these items form the lower blade. The upper one is constrained by our
outlooks as historians. So, for example, I mentioned before Christopher Hill
who would have us believe that the English Civil War was a result of class
conflict. Well, maybe, but if that is our perspective as a historian, it will
colour how the data lands up in our writing. Not that I am accusing anyone of
dishonesty, it is just that a given perspective will inform how the data is
interpreted.
Of course, as wargamers, we are
not quite so interested in how history is done. We would like historians to
give us orders of battle for different armies, detailed investigations about weapons
and so on. Unfortunately, we are more likely to get another article about
homosexuality in Greek antiquity than Alexander’s campaigns in India. The
Academy simply is not interested in the nuts and bolts of warfare.
As rules writers and consumers,
of course, this gives us a bit of a dilemma. We have some older works, the
upper blade of which is assumptions common to the time about history,
imperialism, civilisation and so on. The lower blade is pretty much what we
have, barring a few manuscripts and archaeological finds.
Thus, while we can make our rules
on this basis, some of the core interpretations might not square well with
modern interpretations of what happened. Our rules might reflect some of the older
assumptions, such as the Romans were the good guys and brought civilisation to
much of Europe, or even that the pilum was a super weapon, a cross between a
longbow and a machine gun.
So, as wargamers and wargame rule
writers, we are forced back towards examining our own assumptions about history,
and how they might form the upper blade of our historical analysis. To be sure,
so single synthesis will cover all the historical contingencies of the real
world. Some bits, as with some results of science, will simply have to be
shelved until the next new concept comes along to provide an interpretation.
But, in the world of wargamers in Western liberal democracies we need to
examine some of the assumptions that underlie our own worldview.
Just as an example, it is common
in history just now to talk more about the common people and their experience
than the elite. In wargaming terms, does this mean that the rabble is given
more power than the historical record allows, because we have picked up a prejudice
in their favour? The original writers of chronicles and accounts would have
been elite, after all, and biased against the rabble. Have we over compensated?